A blow to the rights of transgender children

Reubs J Walsh argues that trans children understand their own gender, and should therefore not be assumed to lack the competence to determine their own treatment.

The High Court just dealt a blow to the rights of transgender children in the UK (Bell v. Tavistock, 2020). As a consequence, thousands of trans teenagers have been stripped of the autonomy to access a life-saving medical treatment. The NHS trust affected is seeking permission to appeal.

Reeling from this ruling, I noticed how certain misconceptions about transgender children, which have become much more prevalent in the last few years, may have led to this injustice. So, I thought I would dispel some myths and discuss how these myths are used to justify attacks on trans children’s access to healthcare – sometimes even by gender-specialists (Turban et al., 2017; Temple-Newhook et al., 2018; Winters et al., 2018). 

Accessing healthcare

The case was brought against the Tavistock & Portman’s Gender Identity Development Service (GIDS) (Bell v.Tavistock, 2020), the only NHS service for transgender children in England and Wales. The case rested on the assumption that under-16s cannot be trusted with their medical decisions. The judgement of this case was released on Tuesday and the NHS consequently issued an amendment to GIDS’ service specification that means they cannot continue to refer patients for endocrine treatments that prevent the patient from having to endure a traumatic, gender-incongruent puberty. More detail on how GIDS plan to handle this issue is available on their website, but in short, there is now no way for under-16s in England and Wales to access this vital treatment without first going to court. 

Gillick competence’ is the result of a 1985 landmark ruling (Gillick v. West Norfolk and Wisbech AHA, 1985) that enables children to access healthcare without parental consent if they are ascertained to understand the possible and probable effects of the treatment. Gillick competence is now vulnerable to legal challenge, which could make access to abortion in particular, much harder for under-18s. This is hard to square with the self-described ‘feminism’ of those supporting the case. Even if Gillick had been preserved by a ruling in GIDS’ favour, bringing this case would still have worsened the already difficult situation in which trans children find themselves when seeking support for their identities. This result is a terrible blow to the rights of British youth – especially, but not exclusively, trans youth – to bodily and personal self-determination. 

The only transgender-specific medical treatment offered to under-16s in the UK is GnRHa (Gonadotrophin Releasing Hormone analogues) – commonly known as puberty blockers (PBs). These medications interrupt the progression of puberty, and have been used to treat precocious puberty, even in very young children, safely and successfully for years (Zenaty et al., 2016). Puberty blockers are completely reversible (Manasco et al., 1998; Panagiotakopoulos, 2018) – reversibility is the whole point [Editor's note: Although note the NHS guidance on this]. Children are able to experience just the beginnings of their endogenous puberty, and then pause to take time to make a properly informed decision about what is right for them, their bodies and their genders (Schaagen et al., 2016). 

However, the judgement in Bell v. Tavistock (2020) argues that because most of the GIDS patients who use puberty blockers subsequently move onto irreversible gender-affirming hormone therapy (GAHT), that the blockers may somehow reinforce their (trans)gender identity. It is not made clear why this is more problematic than the reinforcement of a gender identity aligned with the sex assigned at birth. Informed consent to puberty blockers, they argue, therefore requires the patient to also comprehend all of the possible risks and consequences of GAHT as well as PBs. This misinterprets the evidence: the fact that most patients prescribed PBs choose to proceed to GAHT indicates that PBs are generally prescribed to individuals who will benefit from them (given that GAHT is not currently an option before age 16). The existence of a small minority who discontinue their treatment supports the rationale for PBs – that they provide time for the young person to consider their choices regarding permanent treatments like GAHT without the urgency that the onset of a gender-incongruent puberty would otherwise produce. Urgency both in terms of clinical and social outcomes, and subjective feelings of urgency that might make calm, informed decision-making more difficult. Thus it seems PBs are beneficial whichever decision they ultimately facilitate. The judgement also argues that the remaining scientific uncertainties around the longer-term effects of GnRHa would be difficult for an under-18 to adequately comprehend, even though a similar level of uncertainty existed around hormonal contraception when the court ruled in Gillick that under-16s were capable of providing adequate informed consent to access hormonal contraception without the need to seek parental consent.

A continuing identity 

There is a long and sad history of trans people not being believed when we disclose our identities. This is especially true for those who are less normative than the binary categories of feminine women and masculine men – butch trans women, femme trans men, nonbinary, genderqueer, genderfluid or agender people are all less likely to be believed (Riggs et al., 2019). The so-called ‘desistance’ myth, arising from four shoddy papers that shouldn’t have made it past peer review, claimed that 80 per cent of trans-identified children would grow up to be cisgender. 

Children who identify as trans are in fact extremely likely to continue to identify as such, as beautifully explored in a paper debunking the ‘desistance’ myth (Temple-Newhook et al., 2018), which recently deservedly won the Gender Identity Research and Education Society Research Prize. (See Ansara & Hegarty, 2012, for an analysis of how the psychological literature on transgender people came to be dominated by a small number of extremely cisgenderist authors, by exploiting flaws in the peer review system.) The term ‘desistance’ is taken from criminal psychology – it entered the psychological lexicon as an antonym to recidivism, and had not changed from that use until its appropriation for this context (Temple-Newhook et al., 2018). Applying the term here casts merely being transgender as a crime, which is, to say the least, stigmatising.

In debunking the ‘desistance’ myth, Temple-Newhook and colleagues (2018) quote the lead author of two of the four articles which established the myth: ‘explicitly asking children with [gender dysphoria] with which sex they identify seems to be of great value in predicting a future outcome’ (Steensma et al., 2013, p. 588). In other words, kids who say they identify as a particular gender, continue to identify with that gender. This isn’t surprising – cisgender youth tend to continue to be cisgender into adulthood, too. 

Valuing authenticity and agency

Let’s think about this from the point of view of clinical science and the efficacy of ‘tests’. Diagnostic tests rarely get things 100 per cent right 100 per cent of the time, especially where the mind is concerned. Sensitivity is the ability of the test to reliably give a positive result when the entity being tested for is present – the ‘hit’ rate divided by the ‘miss’ rate. Specificity is the ability of the test to reliably give a negative result when the entity is absent – the ‘correct rejection’ rate divided by the false-positive rate (Fawcett, 2006). As diagnostic tests go, the test for assumed-cis youth to be permitted to undergo a gender-congruent (i.e. congruent with their stated or assumed identity) puberty seriously lacks specificity – I am a woman, and I was a girl – but I had an androgen-driven puberty because (quite understandably) nobody bothered to check if it was right for me. 

The ‘desistence’ myth, and society’s general animosity towards transgender people conspire to make sure the diagnostic test for identified trans youth to be permitted to undergo a gender-congruent puberty has a terrible lack of sensitivity. Furthermore, it is an onerous process and surely puts a terrible strain on the child’s sense of self, always being expected to ‘prove’ their identities. Study after study shows how harmful it is to undermine the gender identities of trans people (McLemore, 2015; 2018; Russel et al., 2018; Gridley et al., 2018; see Connelly et al., 2016 for review). My own experience in an adult service felt like a sceptical interrogation – ‘oh, you really think you’re a woman?!’ – sadly, my conversations with trans youth and their parents have convinced me that GIDS patients’ experiences are only slightly better, if at all, which is why I have been a (reluctant) critic of GIDS for some time now.

These false ‘desistance’ figures are sometimes quoted at parents to discourage them from permitting even the most basic parts of a social gender transition, such as changes of name, pronoun and/or clothing. This doesn’t happen at GIDS, but it certainly happens in the media and I’ve heard anecdotal reports that it occurs at a number of clinics in other parts of northwestern Europe. Clearly, given the unreliability of the methodologies in the papers that Temple-Newhook and colleagues (2018) criticise, this assumes that even interrupting a cisgender identity with a voluntary, self-initiated period of self-exploration is a worse approach than one in which the child has the opportunity to explore gender expression freely.

The superficial appearance of a cisgender childhood is preserved by denying children agency, shoving them into a box marked ‘boy’ or ‘girl’ when at the very least, they’d prefer that didn’t happen at the moment please. This framework sees any case of a child living a transgender life when they ‘could have been’ cisgender as a bad outcome – and the lengths some clinics will go to, to prevent this outcome make that transgender life much less liveable. The slimmest possibility of the child being cisgender is protected – at the expense of the child’s most fundamental agency – that over their identity and their body. A hypothetical cisgender child seems to matter more to the current GIDS system than the very real transgender children GIDS is supposed to be helping. Of course, GIDS also receives referrals of cisgender children and children who know that they don’t yet know, and works to support them as they explore and develop their gender and sense of self. However, there are also children who are very clear in their gender identification and will explicitly assert that identity when given the opportunity to do so. It is these children for whom these repeated assessments present problematic delays.

This is a pattern. When it comes to sex and gender (and many other areas of selfhood; see, for example, work around neurodiversity), medical professionals and parents alike prefer normativity to authenticity. Some may say that declining to treat is a neutral option, but when the demands of normativity go the other way, in the case of intersex children, treatment has all too often been inflicted against their wishes (Carpenter, 2016), often in part because of how clinicians have framed their advice to parents (Roen & Hegarty, 2018).

I’m certain that a huge majority of professionals make these decisions from a place of genuinely desiring to do what is in the child’s best interests. But while the struggles associated with being openly trans may be obvious and visible to the outside world, the struggles associated with being trans and closeted are largely hidden. Time and again the literature shows that undermining a trans person’s true gender does enormous harm. Clinicians must be expected to follow evidence-based best practice. Exactly what that means is up for debate, and I’m sure the GIDS team are following that debate closely to work out how best to serve their patients. 

Reducing harm

However, I want to say to GIDS, to everyone: the evidence is clear. When children want to explore a social transition, the potential for harm in letting them choose clothes, pronouns and even a name that make them feel comfortable, is dwarfed by the harm of stopping them and undermining their identity. In one study, for example, simply using an identity-congruent name, chosen by a trans child, in one additional context reduced suicidal ideation by 29 per cent and suicidal behaviours by 56 per cent (Russel et al., 2018). By the time medical interventions become relevant, the likelihood of a child ultimately identifying as cisgender is very small – regret is usually related to a more binary transition than was appropriate for them. This could perhaps be the product of a desire to be perceived as ‘trans enough’ to access treatments, or simply the relative invisibility and unintelligibility (Nicholas, 2018; Walsh & Einstein, 2020) of nonbinary people in our society.

Even for children who are given access to blockers, the system is already painfully slow. Imagine at age 12 your body starts changing in ways you find terrifying, knowing that these changes aren’t reversible, and will lead you to be more visibly trans, more likely to be misgendered or attacked, and cause you to experience increasing distress about the way your gendered embodiment is perceived by yourself or others. Now imagine you can pause it – fantastic news! (Ignoring the waiting lists and assessments which together add up to a minimum of 28 months’ wait before GIDS will consider referring you for blockers – which will now require the extra step of securing the authorisation of a court.) Then they tell you, ‘OK then, now wait four years and then you can start asking about resuming puberty, this time in a gender-congruent way’. Those four years are going to seem long. By the time you’re 16, you’ve spent a quarter of your life paused in early puberty, waiting for the gender-affirmative (hormone) treatment you know will make life so, so much better. Developing on a timeline close to peers is important to trans teens (Gridley et al., 2018). While your friends are going on dates and undergoing this crucial stage of psychosexual development together, you have to wait until they’ve overtaken you by four years. Forcing children to choose between delaying puberty until age 16, or returning to the endogenous puberty that horrified them seems absurd, even cruel to me. 

I’m not alone in this. The ‘affirmative’ model, in which the child’s gender identity and right to assert that identity is affirmed, is much more common in much of the USA and Canada, for instance. This is also known as the ‘informed consent’ model (mostly in adult contexts), because rather than having to ‘prove’ their identities (to a ‘gatekeeper’), patients are instead only required to show they understand what the treatment will do and what the risks and side effects are – it is then up to them to decide whether, when and how to proceed. This approach sees consistently excellent mental health outcomes (Olson et al., 2016) with miniscule rates of regret or desistance (Pullen Sansfaçon et al., 2019). 

Seeing fluidly

It seems to me that the younger generation no longer see identity in the same fixed way that older generations do. Gender (and sexuality) to them is as fluid as other dimensions of identity, such as one’s profession, rather than relatively fixed like race might be. Of course in practice only a very tiny number of people transition more than once in a lifetime, but if we saw multiple transitions as valid (indeed perhaps if we saw gender-transitions in general as valid) we might come to realise that a child who is happy and healthy and transitions twice, is a far preferable outcome to a child whose identity wasn’t adequately supported through a period of flux, whose sense of personal agency was trampled over, and who grows up to be, at least superficially, cisgender.

But what about the fact that they’re still developing cognitively? The limited evidence we have so far indicates that trans youth understand their genders in the same way that cisgender youth do – albeit maybe more deeply (Conron, 2008). Even prepubescent children show the same pattern of explicit and implicit gender cognition, regardless of whether their expressed gender was congruent with assigned sex. For example, one way in which children express their genders is social imitation, wherein preferences for particular objects are biased by the preferences they see in other children of the same gender. Trans and cis girls both tend to express greater preference for objects when told that a child with a female name liked that object, and less preference when the endorsement came from a child with a male name, and the inverse applied to trans and cis boys (Olson et al., 2015). (I always refer to girls and boys based on their identities, not assigned sex; please do the same!)

Speaking up 

So trans children know their own gender, yet refusal to provide access to GAHT until age 16 is currently a hard and fast rule in GIDS, and now they’ll likely need a court’s permission to prevent the harms of a gender-incongruent puberty. All of this is to ‘protect’ the child from their own decisions. This is the real scandal in paediatric gender-care, this is the unproven treatment protocol, and this is how GIDS have consistently failed to deliver care on a truly informed-consent basis. ‘Protecting’ people from their own bodily autonomy hasn’t gone well in the past. Criminalising consensual sex, withholding contraception from unmarried women, legislation against interracial marriage – and now, trans children’s genders. Why isn’t this the trans healthcare issue in the newspapers, on Panorama and in the courts?

We know why. Trans children’s parents, unless they can afford to go overseas or can find some other alternative route to treatment, have to rely entirely on GIDS, so they daren’t rock the boat. They cannot litigate this issue because to do so would put them in direct conflict with the people who hold the only key to their child’s wellbeing. GIDS staff are constantly portrayed in the media as dangerous for the essential care they provide to children; it’s no wonder they end up taking overly conservative approaches, and even then they face litigation. If the court cares about the alleged ‘unknown potential risks’ of GnRHa, why didn’t they ask why children are required to wait so long before being permitted a gender-congruent puberty? 

Unless they see a trans life as of inferior moral worth to a cis one?  

So, I am asking you, dear reader, to speak up on behalf of trans kids. When GIDS is attacked for the many important things they do get right – speak up. When GIDS gives in to pressure to value hypotheticals over real children – speak up. When the people whose job it is to protect trans children, to care for them and to help them cope with a world that would rather they didn’t exist, when the people trans children and their families are supposed to trust, fail them – speak up. Whether it’s the Minister for Women and Equalities, a judge, doctor, teacher or psychologist, or even their parents – don’t be a bystander.

-       Reubs Walsh, PhD candidate, Vrije Universiteit Amsterdam

Editor's note: The full judgement, which has been linked from the first sentence of this piece, is also available here.

References

Ansara, Y.G. & Hegarty, P. (2011). Cisgenderism in psychology: Pathologising and misgendering children from 1999 to 2008. Psychology and Sexuality3(2), 137-160. https://doi.org/10.1080/19419899.2011.576696

Bell v. Tavistock [2020] EWHC 3274 (Admin). https://www.judiciary.uk/wp-content/uploads/2020/12/Bell-v-Tavistock-Jud...

Carpenter, M. (2016). The human rights of intersex people: Addressing harmful practices and rhetoric of change. Reproductive Health Matters24(47), 74-84. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.rhm.2016.06.003

Connolly, M.D., Zervos, M.J., Barone, C.J. et al. (2016). The mental health of transgender youth: Advances in understanding. Journal of Adolescent Health, 59(5), 489-495. doi:10.1016/j.jadohealth.2016.06.012

Conron, K.J., Scout & Austin, S.B. (2008). “Everyone has a right to, like, check their box:” Findings on a measure of gender identity from a cognitive testing study with adolescents. Journal of LGBT Health Research, 4(1), 1-9. doi:10.1080/15574090802412572

Fawcett, T. (2006). An introduction to ROC Analysis. Pattern Recognition Letters, 27(8), 861-874. doi:10.1016/j.patrec.2005.10.010

Gridley, S.J., Crouch, J.M., Evans, Y. et al. (2016). Youth and caregiver perspectives on barriers to gender-affirming health care for transgender youth. Journal of Adolescent Health59(3), 254-261. Doi:10.1016/j.jadohealth.2016.03.017

Manasco, P.K., Pescovitz, O.H., Feuillan, P.P. et al. (1988). Resumption of puberty after long term luteinizing hormone-releasing hormone agonist treatment of central precocious puberty. Journal of Clinical Endocrinology and Metabolism67(2), 368-372. doi:10.1210/jcem-67-2-368

McLemore, K.A. (2015). Experiences with misgendering: identity misclassification of transgender spectrum individuals. Self and Identity14(1), 51-74. doi:10.1080/15298868.2014.950691

McLemore, K.A. (2018). A minority stress perspective on transgender individuals’ experiences with misgendering. Stigma and Health3(1), 53-64. doi:10.1037/sah0000070

Nicholas, L. (2018). Queer ethics and fostering positive mindsets toward non-binary gender, genderqueer, and gender ambiguity. International Journal of Transgenderism, 20(2-3), 169-180. doi:10.1080/15532739.2018.1505576

Olson, K.R., Key, A.C. & Eaton, N.R. (2015). Gender cognition in transgender children. Psychological Science26(4). doi:10.1177/0956797614568156

Olson, K.R., Durwood, L., DeMeules, M. & McLaughlin, K.A. (2016). Mental health of transgender children who are supported in their identities. Pediatrics137(3), 1-8. doi:10.1542/peds.2015-3223

Panagiotakopoulos, L. (2018). Transgender medicine - puberty suppression. Reviews in Endocrine and Metabolic Disorders19(3), 221-225. doi:10.1007/s11154-018-9457-0

Pullen Sansfaçon, A., Temple-Newhook, J., Suerich-Gulick, F. et al. (2019). The experiences of gender diverse and trans children and youth considering and initiating medical interventions in Canadian gender-affirming speciality clinics. International Journal of Transgenderism20(4), 371-387. https://doi.org/10.1080/15532739.2019.1652129

Riggs, D.W., Pearce, R., Pfeffer, C.A. et al. (2019). Transnormativity in the psy disciplines: Constructing pathology in the diagnostic and statistical manual of mental disorders and standards of care. American Psychologist, 74, 912-924.

Roen, K. & Hegarty, P. (2018). Shaping parents, shaping penises: How medical teams frame parents' decisions in response to hypospadias. British Journal of Health Psychology, 23, 967-981.

Russell, S.T., Pollitt, A.M., Li, G. & Grossman, A.H. (2018). Chosen name use is linked to reduced depressive symptoms, suicidal ideation, and suicidal behavior among transgender youth. Journal of Adolescent Health, 63(4), 503-505. doi:10.1016/j.jadohealth.2018.02.003 

Schagen, S.E., Cohen-Kettenis, P.T., Delemarre-van de Waal, H.A. & Hannema, S.E. (2016). Efficacy and safety of gonadotropin-releasing hormone agonist treatment to suppress puberty in gender dysphoric adolescents. The Joural of Sexual Medicine13(7), 1125‐1132. doi:10.1016/j.jsxm.2016.05.004

Steensma, T., McGuire, J., Kreukels, B. et al. (2013). Factors associated with desistance and persistence of childhood gender dysphoria: A quantitative follow-up study. Journal of the American Academy of Child & Adolescent Psychiatry, 52(6), 582-590. doi:10.1016/j.jaac.2013.03.016 

Temple Newhook, J., Pyne, J., Winters, K. et al. (2018). A critical commentary on follow-up studies and “desistance” theories about transgender and gender-nonconforming children. International Journal of Transgenderism19(2), 212-224. https://doi.org/10.1080/15532739.2018.1456390

Turban, J., Ferraiolo, T., Martin, A. & Olezeski, C. (2017). Ten things transgender and gender nonconforming youth want their doctors to know. Journal of the American Academy of Child and Adolescent Psychiatry56(4), 275-277. doi:10.1016/j.jaac.2016.12.015

Walsh, R.J. & Einstein, G. (2020). Transgender embodiment: a feminist, situated neuroscience perspective. Journal of the International Network for Sexual Ethics and Politics8(si2020) 56-70. https://doi.org/10.3224/insep.si2020.04

Winters, K., Temple Newhook, J., Pyne, J. et al. (2018). Learning to listen to trans and gender diverse children: A response to Zucker (2018) and Steensma and Cohen-Kettenis (2018). International Journal of Transgenderism, 19(2), 246-250. doi:10.1080/15532739.2018.1471767

Zenaty, D., Blumberg, J., Liyanage, N. et al. (2016). A 6-month trial of the efficacy and safety of triptorelin pamoate (11.25 mg) every 3 months in children with precocious puberty: a retrospective comparison with triptorelin acetate. Hormone Research in Paediatrics, 86(3), 188-195. doi:10.1159/000448840 

BPS Members can discuss this article

Already a member? Or Create an account

Not a member? Find out about becoming a member or subscriber

Comments

At the risk of an instant accusation of transphobia, I am here to express serious concern that the house journal of The British Psychological Society has thought fit to actively commission an article with this very particular direct response to the Judicial Review and publish it within days of the Review making public its findings. I am not here to challenge various points made in the article which can better be discussed by current child development researchers and mental health practitioner. It is to question the failure of the Society and this journal to recognise a responsibility to members who are placed in the position of having to work with and support distressed young people and families. Unless subsequently overturned at an appeal, the Judicial Review constitutes a decision about the lawful behaviour of professionals around the issue of capacity to consent, and makes reference to the inadequacy of the evidence base around outcomes, much of which relates directly to psychological wellbeing.

 

As of this moment there remains in place the BPS document https://www.bps.org.uk/news-and-policy/guidelines-psychologists-working-gender-sexuality-and-relationship-diversity  which a practitioner may well now wish to consult. Such a practitioner may be unaware that these guidelines have generated considerable controversy and demands for their withdrawal subject to significant revisions https://thepsychologist.bps.org.uk/volume-33/october-2020/freedom-expression-around-diversity-guidelines . These guidelines make the following statements directly relevant to the Judicial Review’s focus on puberty blockers and capacity to consent:

Psychologists working with GSRD youth should be aware that reproductive options and considerations may be more complex than with their heterosexual or cisgender peers. Assistive reproductive options may be needed and should be discussed openly and frankly, perhaps especially in the case of trans youth who are seeking treatments which will remove reproductive options at an age below that which people commonly consider becoming a parent”.

The Psychologist printed an unattributed “Society Response” which made the following categoric and clearly untrue pronouncement: “our guidance is specifically for the care and treatment of adults, not children.”.  GSRD youth has a whole section in the guidelines. The paragraph quoted above also relates very specifically to issues around discussions of consent to treatments which will affect fertility in adult life. The implication is that psychologists would be able to ensure by open and frank discussion with a young person that they would be capable of understanding later outcomes and remedies.  The judges disagreed.

 

It is now possible that practitioners find themselves engaged with young people and families who seek to obtain puberty blockers from various illicit sources. This puts the clinician in a very difficult position, practically, ethically and legally. From the above it is clear that they will get no helpful and responsible reference point from their professional body’s present stance, be it this polemical article attacking the Judicial Review that The Psychologist chose to commission and foreground at this juncture, or from the guidelines that remain in place. Guidelines which the Society refuses to withdraw and revise, which they say don’t apply to children, but clearly do.

 

 

We are not a 'house journal', we are a magazine. Our responsibility is not to speak for the Society or to align with any documents it might publish; it is to provide a forum for communication, discussion and controversy among members and beyond.  

The Walsh article is an opinion piece which you are free to disagree with, on here or via a letter. I note you have already had a say on the topic in print here.

The editorial team approached Reubs Walsh at the beginning of the year, originally about writing (on a voluntary basis) on gender diversity and autism. Inevitably as the legal case developed, that became more of a focus, and as we had the article ready to go (with some amends once the outcome was known), that seemed a good time to put it on the website. Part of a magazine's role is to be topical, particularly with its online presence. 

All readers are free to agree with the article (many have), disagree with it, ignore it, as they choose. We will continue to provide that forum for discussion and debate, and will not be stifled by any responsibility to side with a particular position.

Dr Jon Sutton
Managing Editor

I regret that the editor’s response “we are a magazine” diverts from the very serious comments I have made about responsibility to members.

When is a magazine rather more than a magazine? Maybe when it is “the official monthly publication of The British Psychological Society”, “  https://thepsychologist.bps.org.uk/about

When it is “unique”, has “a paid editor who is a member of staff” , when “Policy development and editorial decision making for The Psychologist are subject to this overarching consideration: The object of the Society stated in the Royal Charter is to promote the advancement and diffusion of a knowledge of psychology pure and applied and especially to promote the efficiency and usefulness of Members of the Society by setting up a high standard of professional education and knowledge.” (https://thepsychologist.bps.org.uk/sites/thepsychologist.bps.org.uk/files/pdfs/Psychologist%20Policy%281%29.pdf (2009)

 

I note that The Psychologist is not listed as a magazine signed up to IPSO, so I am unable to report to them that it has printed a statement from the Society that is patently false - in order to attempt to secure a retraction in print and online.

 

Why has there not been a retraction? The Society statement was not correct - the guidelines clearly refer to GSRD youth and in the context of medication and consent refer to having professional conversations with persons of an age “below that which people commonly consider becoming a parent”. This is the issue right at the heart of the Judicial Review.

 

The editor states “We…. will not be stifled by any responsibility to side with a particular position.” Where does that leave siding with simple truth? And of course, the law?

 

I have no more to add to this discussion, save that I have once more written to the Presidents, current, vice and elect, asking that the guidelines be immediately withdrawn and revised, and a statement made to that effect. i ask this for the benefit of psychology practitioners who are dealing with very difficult professional issues in their every day working lives.

 

...I like that.

The 'truth' is not always so simple, and the 'law' can be questioned.

By all means submit a letter to us on [email protected] regarding the Society statement.

Best wishes 

Jon

...and just to add, I'll look into IPSO membership, thanks for the tip.

Jon

I will absolutely enquire about the Society statement.

Thanks again 

Jon